Positive Liberty, 1880–1914
- 1 March 1962
- journal article
- Published by Cambridge University Press (CUP) in American Political Science Review
- Vol. 56 (1) , 114-128
- https://doi.org/10.2307/1953101
Abstract
It would not, I think, be entirely misleading to suggest that doctrines of laissez faire and attacks upon reasoned state intervention in political and social life have tended to emanate from two extremes in social philosophy—ultra individualism and an extreme organicism. In the first case, and we may take Locke as an example, society is made up of a heap of individuals who came together to form the state for the limited purpose of the protection of property. Man is not seen as a part of a larger whole, influenced by the structure of that whole, but as an isolated individual; thus any state interference beyond the protection of property is viewed as a restriction of individual liberty. On the other hand are thinkers who regard society as such a complicated and delicate organism that they can only—and governments should only—sit back and gasp at the complexity of it all. Any attempt to improve one aspect will affect the balance of the whole in ways impossible to predict. It is difficult to point to a pure instance of this opinion, but this is the impression left with the reader after perusing such works as Burke's Reflections on the Revolution in France, Hegel's Philosophy of Right, Bradley's Ethical Studies and the works of some more modern conservatives. All that governments can be expected to do is to prevent the worst collisions and any attempt to pursue a positive policy is doomed to failure.Keywords
This publication has 4 references indexed in Scilit:
- Natural RightsPublished by Taylor & Francis ,2014
- Community and AssociationBritish Journal of Sociology, 1956
- The Working Faith of the Social Reformer.The Economic Journal, 1910
- Social Evolution.Benjamin KiddThe International Journal of Ethics, 1894