Ethical debate: Informed consent in medical research Informed consent---a response to recent correspondence Changing the BMJ's position on informed consent would be counterproductive Informed consent---a publisher's duty Trial subjects must be fully involved in design and approval of trials Studies that do not have informed consent from participants should not be published
- 28 March 1998
- Vol. 316 (7136) , 1000-1005
- https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.316.7136.1000
Abstract
# Informed consent in medical research {#article-title-2} In the issue of 12 April 1997 the BMJ invited comment on the acceptable limits of informed consent in medical studies. In view of the large correspondence this generated, we invited the two original commentators, Len Doyal and Jeffrey Tobias, to revisit the subject. We also invited comments from three people who are not doctors, researchers, or medical ethicists: two of them represent the views of patients and potential patients # Informed consent—a response to recent correspondence {#article-title-3} Editorial by Smith and Personal views pp 1026-7 The publication of the debate between myself and Jeffrey Tobias about the acceptable limits of informed consent in medical research has generated an immense and varied number of letters to the BMJ .1–4 This in itself is gratifying, whether or not correspondents agree with my arguments. It provides ample evidence of widespread and serious deliberation about the moral boundaries of the rights of participants in research. Previous articles and comment on informed consent are available on our website (see Collections) Many correspondents either explicitly or implicitly endorse the hard line that I take in my paper on the right of competent people to an acceptable level of information before agreeing to participate in medical research. Other contributions confirm my emphasis on the moral importance of the principle of informed consent but, in light of the highly specific circumstances where I argue that the principle must be qualified, question the degree or clarity of my own commitment to it. What is important here is our shared belief in the moral imperative of respecting human autonomy in almost all circumstances. I still disagree with those authors who argue that it is not necessary to obtain informed consent if this will lead to the methodological compromise, or possible cancellation, of potentially beneficial studies involving clinical interventions that carry minimal risks. What these …Keywords
This publication has 26 references indexed in Scilit:
- Informed consent. The central problem is often poor design and conduct of trials.1997
- Informed consent. Lack of respect for patients in medical research may reflect wider disrespect in clinical practice.1997
- Informed consent. "Blanket" consent to trials would be a good idea.1997
- Informed consentBMJ, 1997
- Informed consent in medical researchBMJ, 1997
- Commentary: Why we didn't ask patients for their consentBMJ, 1997
- Consent, Confidentiality, and ResearchNew England Journal of Medicine, 1997
- Reply from dissenting authorBMJ, 1996
- Psychological support for patients undergoing breast cancer surgery: a randomised studyBMJ, 1996
- Fully informed consent can be needlessly cruel.BMJ, 1993